Monday, May 27, 2019
Principles of Public International Law Essay
Law forget never re completelyy play an effective part in globalist relations until it cornerstone annex to its own sphere m only of the matters which at present lie within the domestic jurisdiction of the several utters. Discuss The principles and regulations schematic in a community by some agentity and applicable to its people, whether in the form of legislation or of custom and policies cutd. The aforementioned is a definition of practice of legal philosophy as defined by the American Heritage dictionary of the English Language.If we apply this definition of community in its strictest sense it becomes progressively difficult to subscribe to the view that there is an international community at large. If we begin to analyse statistics that show that there argon over 7000 languages in the world, more or less 10,000 distinctly different religions, and a disputably infinite number of ethnic groups across just the 195 countries that comprise our international society, then it becomes patently clear that we would be mitigate off highlighting our divisiveness rather than our prospects as a global community.Our collective history as human existences, however, tells a different story about our ordinary worry and the way in which we sport formally raised and torn down barriers to promote the same. We have, on the other hand, been separated on the basis of differing ideologies and the exercising of exclusive nationalism. Since the latter is a sentiment which resides in particular nations which have at their core a dictated effective framework validating their truly existence and their interaction with other nations, it is essential to any study of laws application to international relations.How does a sovereign nation reconcile its real reign with its growing need to be integrated into a shrinking global society with its concomitant shrinking global economy? It is clear that some compromises mustiness be made. Before we consider any specific cases in which states have decided to relinquish some of their sovereign power, we must consider the implications of the edge sovereignty itself, the elements of sovereignty and its importance to a nation-state. Much has been written on the topic of sovereignty.Definitions vary slightly from one text to the other hardly they all have at their core, when specifically referring to the idea of state sovereignty, the idea of legitimate authority. In Sohail H. Hashmis discourse on sovereignty in the book present sovereignty, Change and Resistance in International Relations, he asserts, referring to the concept of legitimate authority, that it is a broad concept non a definition only when a wide category that unites most of sovereigntys tradition. He further notes that authority can be defined as The right to direct and correlatively, the right to be obeyed and is only legitimate when it is seen as right by those living under it. It is to be noted that legitimate authority is not merely the idea of more power. R. P. Wolf, the twentieth century political philosopher and individual anarchist, illustrates the difference more sharply in a classical example in which he argues if I am forced at gun localize to hand over my money, I am subject to power if I pay my taxes even though I think I can cheat I am recognizing legitimate authority. We must realize, however, that though legitimate authority is the overarching principle on any discourse on state sovereignty, there are specific elements of state sovereignty that are crucial, which every sovereign state implements dear to it and attempts to retain heedless of seemingly necessary or stipulated concessions of power, influence or authority to the international community. They include International Legal Validation (of a sovereign state), Interdependence Sovereignty and Domestic Sovereignty. International Legal Validation can be viewed as the right of the state to be a sovereign entity as prescribed by inte rnational law.It is legitimate authority as a legal construct or as Hashami puts it legitimate authority that is prescribed by the law. (Hashami, pg 18) The author Stephen D. Krasner in his book Sovereignty, Organised Hypocrisy describes this element of sovereignty as international legal sovereignty. He states that it refers to the practices associated with mutual recognition, usually between territorial entities that have formal juridical independence. At its core international legal validation concerns retorts of the recognition of states.If one were ignorant about the political climate on the global front, the natural answer to the question how did a state become a state? would be that the would-be state must satisfy the defined stipulations (in international law) for becoming a state. Following this line of reasoning would inevitably lead one to the very first article of the Montevideo Convention on Rights and Duties of States, which since 1933 set out that The state, as a person of international law should possess the following qualifications (a) permanent population (b) a defined territory (c) government and (d) capableness to work out into relations with other states. It does not take much political savvy, however, to understand that the legal criteria for statehood and the actual criteria for being recognized as a state by the international community at large is a de facto and de jure issue. As Krasner postulates States have recognized other governments even when they did not have control over their claimed territory, such(prenominal) as the German and Italian recognition of the Franco regime in 1936, and the American recognition of the Lon Nol government in Cambodia in 1970.States have continued to recognize governments which have lost power, including Mexican recognition of the Spanish republican regime of 1977, and recognition of the Chinese Nationalist regime by all of the major westerly powers until the 1970s. States have refused to recog nize new governments even when they have established effective control, such as the British refusal to recognize the July monarch in France until 1832, the US refusal to recognise the Soviet regime until 1934. (Krasner, pg 15) The recognition of states is definitely an area in which the law (as prescribed by the Montevideo Convention and more recently the EU, which has almost resembling tenets concerning the recognition of states) has proved ineffective in international relations precisely because of the political agendas and consequently domestic jurisdiction of the several states which reflect the political climate in which they operate.States attempt to hold on to this type of sovereignty because it affords them clout and validation in a global society in which interdependence is not just an ideal but a tool for survival, at the very least and a necessary aid to prosperity at the very most. The point here is not that nonrecognition brings with it a form of absolute isolation whi ch renders the unrecognised state permanently barred from international commerce and diplomatic relations.What is of paramount importance, however, is the fact that nonrecognition brings with it an air of uncertainty concerning the unrecognised state, particularly in the eyes of multinational firms which as a result may be more reluctant to invest. Krasner notes that by facilitating accords, international legal sovereignty offers the possibility for rulers to secure external resources that can enhance their ability to stay in power and promote the security, economic, and ideational interest of their constituents. (Krasner, pg 17) Interdependence sovereignty is the ability of a state to regulate the flow of information, goods, ideas and people into and out of its country. States try to hold on to this type of sovereignty because their ability to do this is directly related to their ability to effectively take control and organise their own polity, which in essence is domestic sovere ignty which states must hold on to by definition i. e. in order to be a state in the first place.We shall consider reasons which prompt states to relinquish some of their sovereignty later in our discussion. We have then far acknowledged, via several examples, based on the politics involved in the process of mutual recognition of states, that the issue of international legal sovereignty or international legal validation is a de facto versus de jure consideration. Is this, however, a trend in the legal procedures in international relations? The law, based on our previously defined definition, must be applicable to the actors in the community in hich it is operating. If, in the realm of international relations, the law can be voluntarily and regularly flouted by those who come under its subjection then serious questions arise about the very existence of international law. It must be duly noted though that states undeniably operate within the workings of a law order which to a large close regulates their day to day interactions with one another and which is autonomous in its operations. There are a countless number of international treatises that are steadfastly ascertained on a day to day basis.Examples include international accordances which facilitate the smooth to and fro transport of letters which are transported to all corners of the globe at meliorate rates which are stipulated by the Universal postal union, the establishment of hundreds of football leagues worldwide- the individual countries who oversee them all subscribing to the specific rules and regulation set out by the world governing personify in football, F. I. F. A. and the Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations which afford diplomats exemption from prosecution within the courts of the country in which they are stationed.It is evident then that there is a legal framework that regulates the goings on of international relations. We have to probe a bit deeper into the workings of this bras s in order to ascertain whether or not it can accurately be characterised as international law. It can be argued that upon examination of our above examples of situations in which law plays an effective role in international relations, that the circumstances demand that such broad and far-reaching legal action be undertaken. The methods may vary but in order for letters to be transported globally there must be some standardisation procedure.This sort of necessary self-coercion can be observed in a slightly different manner in the operations of international trade wind and commerce. Often times when two countries have a trade dispute they seek to resolve it in the World Trade Organisation (W. T. O. ), the foremost international authority on trade and trade disputes. The country that loses the dispute, in a legal case which is heard before a court of law under the auspices of the W. T. O. , more often that not abides by the decision. This, a come on, is not necessarily because the lo sing party has a great respect or reverence for international law or the W.T. O. per se, but rather because it is within its interest to do so. As Harris explains, The great majority of the rules of international law are generally observed by all nations without actual compulsion, for it is generally in the interest of all nations concerned to honour their obligations under international law. (Harris pg 8) He further argues that a nation will be reluctant to disregard its obligations under a technical treaty, since the benefits that it expects from the execution of the treaty by the other contracting parties are complimentary to those anticipated by the latter.It may thus stand to loose more than it would gain by not fulfilling its part in the bargain. This is particularly so in the long run since a nation that has the reputation of reneging on its commercial obligations will find it hard to conclude commercial treaties beneficially to itself. (Harris pg8) There is, evidently the n, a law amongst nations, which is effective regardless of the reason for it being so. The problem of specify this law amongst nations as international law, however, lies in part because of those very cases in which it is flagrantly disregarded.For any legal system to be givenal optimally it must operate in a community in which there is a legislative system to make laws as it sees fit, a judiciary to implement the politics of justice and an executive body to enforce the law. Now grant it, generally speaking, there is no formal legislative system in international relations, when countries enter into agreements with each other the signing of treaties is usually undertaken and this serves as the source of law that is meant to dictate the terms of their agreement. However, unlike what is the case in municipal law, there is no definite enforceability method.There is no one authority that can guarantee the compliance of states to international treaties or conventions. We have already m ade the point that in most cases compliance has become second nature but what of the cases (though they are scarce) in which it is not? Within the domestic law arena there are cases in which the law is glaringly broken. Once there is enough evidence to convict the wrongdoer, he is convicted and punished. The punitive measures that are undertaken would have been pre-determined by the legislative body and subsequently enforced by an executive body.There is no such arrangement in the international domain. As Harris puts forward The problem of enforcement becomes acute, however, in that nonage of important and generally spectacular cases, particularly important in the context of our discussion, in which compliance with international law and its enforcement have a direct military strength on the relative power of the nations concerned. In those casesconsiderations of power rather than of law determine compliance and enforcement. (Harris, pg 9) Therein lies the difficulty in saying tha t there is a law of nations.Having established the problematic nature of international law or a law of nations, we shall henceforth temporarily ignore our challenges with nomenclature for the purposes of our remaining discussion. That being said, it is of critical importance to analyse the impact of international law on municipal law and vice versa. There is an ongoing dispute between theorizer who believe that international law and municipal law are two separate legal orders and theorist who believe that they are part of the same legal order. The formative argument is known as dualism while the latter is known as monism.There is no one argument based on either monism or dualism that comprehensively settles the dispute. On the international plane, international law is invoked and applied on a daily basis by states and intergovernmental organisations. With minor exceptions, it is the only law that applies to the conduct of states and international organisations in their relations w ith one another. Here international law is a distinct legal system, comparable in its scope and function to a national legal system. (Buergenthal-Murphy, pg 3)The point mentioned above is very valid and gives credence to the dualism argument. Diplomatic relations, as discussed earlier, are dealt with strictly on the international plane. In order to see the appeal of the monism argument however we have to look no further than the argument establishing the Caribbean Court of Justice (C. C. J. ). Article XXIII of this agreement is as follows 1)Each contracting party should, to the maximum extent possible, encourage and facilitate the use of arbitration and other means of alternative dispute resolution for the closure of international commercial disputes. )To this end, each contracting party shall provide appropriate procedures to ensure observance of agreements to arbitrate and for the recognition and enforcement of arbitral award in such disputes. The C. C. J. is a court whose aim i s to have a determinative role in the further development of Caribbean jurisprudence through the juridical process is thus an international legal authority. In order for its smooth operation it must nevertheless depend on the domestic jurisdictions of its member states. Monism and dualism can hence be viewed as fluid concepts which exist in varying degrees.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment